Some conservatives are immensely more fun to debate thanย others.
In the past month, a debate over left-right science abuse with Kenneth Green of the American Enterprise Institute led to him hurling charges of โsocialism.โย Notย kidding.
Unfortunately, โCarol Browner is a socialistโ isnโt an argument. Itโs a heuristic device. Itโs the kind of thing you say if you want to get emotive Tea Party reasoners whippedย up.
Ron Bailey of the Reason magazine is, in contrast, full ofโฆreason. He weighed in last weekย on this topic, went through the issues, and came down slightly differently than I did on some of them, but actually agreed that the GOP is doing much worse now with respect toย science.
In the process, Ron also made me pretty concerned about Democrats and GM salmon. If thereโs no serious risk hereโand Ron and also this piece at Science Progress make a strong case that wayโthen we shouldnโt be scare-mongering about thisย technology.
I want to say a few things about Ronโs commentary, though, because I think it still has some flaws. In particular, I want to take on his criticism of the so-called โprecautionary principle,โ which he charges is โunscientific in the sense that it demands the impossible: Researchers can never show that any technological or scientific activity will never produce significantย harm.โ
Even this would not be โunscientificโ by my definition. It would still be a moral or policy position, albeit an indefensibleย one.
But of course, this is not what precaution, in a reasonable sense, actually means. Ron Baileyโs own source on this matter, Obama administration OMB official Cass Sunstein, agrees withย me:
I have suggested that the weak versions of the precautionary principle are unobjectionable and important. Every day, people take steps (and incur costs) to avoid hazards that are far from certain. We do not walk in moderately dangerous areas at night; we exercise; we buy smoke detectors; we buckle our seatbelts; we might even avoid fatty foods. Sensible governments are willing to consider regulation of risks that, in individual cases or even in the aggregate, have a well under 100% chance of coming to fruition. The weak versions of the precautionary principle state a truismโuncontroversial and necessary only to combat public confusion or the self-interested claims of private groups demanding unambiguous evidence of harm, which no rational society requires. This function should not be trivialized. Nearly aย fifth of Americans, for example, recently agreed that โuntil we are sure that global warming is really a problem, we should not take any steps that would have economic costs.โ Sometimes people do seem to seek certainty before showing a willingness toย expend costs, and well-organized private groups like to exploit this fact. Insofar as the precautionary principle counteracts the tendency to demand certainty, it should beย approved.
This โweakโ version of the precautionary principle is certainly the one I would espouse. Obviously, you canโt demand that any person introducing any new product, service, or activity must first prove conclusively that no harm will ever come from it before allowing anything to go forward. That would throw total sand in the gears of everything, and is certainly not how precaution is practiced in the United States (where the government regulatory structure nevertheless remains, to my mind, broadlyย precautionary).
If you were to apply precaution in this mindless way, you could make a case that we should still be worried about vaccines and autism. Despite the many epidemiological studies and scientific consensus reports that have shown thereโs no reason to worry about this risk, we’re definitely not, like,ย certainย โthat vaccines areย safe.
But if you apply precaution in my and Sunsteinโs weak version, you don’t worry about vaccines but you do end up very very concerned about global warming. Because we know itโs real, and while thereโs much uncertainty about the range and speed of the impacts, it is precisely that uncertainty that’s so disturbingโbecause the magnitude of the consequences couldย staggering.
So you donโt apply precaution when there isn’t any evidence of anything to worry about. Rather, when there is good evidence that you have something to worry about but you donโt know how bad it is going to beโand it could be quite badโprecaution becomes a sensible policyย indeed.
How do you make the distinction? You weigh the best science, plain and simple. And if it doesn’t suggest a riskโas in the vaccine caseโthen move on. There are many, many other things worth worryingย about.
Have environmentalists ever gone a bit overboard with the precautionary principle? Sure they have. Iโve certainly heard it invoked as a slogan, rather than a sensible policy to address situations involving real but unknown risk. And I agree that itโs a misuse of the principle to wield it against technologies, like GM crops, where scientific consensus reports show the risk to humans isnโt a bigย deal.
So all that is conceded. But letโs remember too: This is really a nuance in our broad debate over left-right scienceย abuse.
Whatโs actually happening out there in the world, on the right wing, is far more extreme than gaming the precautionary principle. We’re talking about utter and often willful denial of scientific reality, including by leading policymakers and presidentialย candidates.
These people worry me, and I have evidence to support my concern. So I think we should employ the precautionary principle againstย further political triumphs by anti-scienceย ideologues.
The weak version, of courseโstronglyย applied.
Subscribe to our newsletter
Stay up to date with DeSmog news and alerts